Bilim Felsefesi Bilim Pratiğinden Ne Öğrenebilir?

Dünya’da bilim felsefesi çalışmaları büyük oranda “bilim pratiğini” odak noktası haline getirmişken, Türkiye’de zaten çok fazla ilgi görmeyen bilim felsefesi çalışmaları henüz bu değişimi yakalayamamıştır; Türkiye’deki bilim felsefesi çalışmaları daha çok bilim felsefesi tarihi veya bilim tarihi olarak adlandırılabilir. Pratik odaklı bilim felsefesine göre bilimi anlamak için analiz ve kavramların anlamlarını açıklama çabaları gerekli olsa da bu tek başına yeterli değildir. Bilim insanlarının çalışma pratiğini belli bir amaç doğrultusunda, tercihen, felsefecilerin dışarıdan dayattıkları ile değil bilim insanlarının kendileri tarafından belirlenen bir amaç doğrultusunda incelemeleri daha anlamlıdır. Bu makalede bilim felsefesi ve bilim pratiği arasındaki karşılıklı ilişkiyi durum çalışmalarından hareketle inceleyerek ana akım bilim felsefesi yerine bilim pratiğini odağa alan yaklaşımın doğru şekilde kavrandığında yöntem olarak bilim felsefesinin normatif/betimleyici ikileminden bağımsız şekilde ele alınabilmesinin yollarını göstermesi açısından daha verimli olduğunu iddia ediyorum.

What can Philosophy of Science Learn from Scientific Practice?

While studies on philosophy of science focus on the scientific practice itself in global level, the present state of philosophy of science in Turkey, which is an underrepresented field of philosophy already, seems to be slow to recognize this change. In fact, studies in philosophy of science in Turkey are generally being conflated with the studies in history of philosophy of science or history of science. According to practice-oriented philosophy of science, although analysis and explication of meaning of concepts may be necessary to understand science, this activity alone would not be sufficient. This approach also holds the view that scientific practices should be evaluated against a purpose, preferably one that is pursued by the scientists themselves and not imposed from outside by a philosopher. In this study, based on some case studies, I investigate the reciprocal relationship between scientific practice and philosophy of science and I claim that instead of what is called mainstream philosophy of science, practice-oriented philosophy of science, if it is conceived in a prop er way, is a more fruitful methodological approach to take as it sheds light on the ways philosophy of science could be saved from normative/descriptive dichotomy.

___

  • Ateş, M. E. (2015). Bilimlerde Düşünce Deneyleri. Akdeniz İnsani Bilimler Dergisi, 125-138.
  • Banks, E. C. (2005). Kant, Herbart , Riemann. Kant Studies, Vol. 96, Issue 2, 208-234.
  • Baigrie, B. S. (1995). Scientific Practice, The View From the Tabletop.” Scientific practice: Theories and Stories of Doing Physics J. Z. Buchwald (Edt.), içinde (ss. 87-122). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Batterman, R. W., Rice, C. C. (2014). Minimal Model Explanations. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 81, No. 3, 349-276.
  • Boas, G. (1951). The Influence of Philosophy on the Sciences. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, Vol. 95, No. 5, 528-537.
  • Buchwald, J. Z. (Ed.) (1995). Scientific Practice: Theories and Sstories of Doing Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Canales, J. (2005). Einstein, Bergson, and the Experiment That Failed: Intellectual Cooperation at the League of Nations. MLN, Vol. 120, No. 5, Comparative Literature Issue, 1168-1191.
  • Canales, J. (2015). The Physicist and the Philosopher: Einstein, Bergson, and the Debate That Changed Our Understanding of Time. Princeton University Press: Princeton and Oxford.
  • Chang, H. (2014). “Epistemic Activities and Systems of Practice.” Science after the Practice Turn in the Philosophy, History, and Social Studies of Science, Lena Soler, Sjoerd Zwart, Michael Lynch, and Vincent Israel-Jost (Eds.) içinde (ss. 123–150). Routledge: New York and London.
  • Çevik, A.D. (2015). Riemann’ın Geometri Felsefesinde Uzay Görüsünün Yeri Var mı? Beytülhikme Felsefe Dergisi, IV Sayı: 1, Cilt: 5, 81-94.
  • Çifteci., V. (2017). Bergson'da Zaman, Kendilik ve Özgürlük. Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 7 (2), 105-122.
  • De Regt, H. W. (2017). Understanding Scientific Understanding. Oxford University Press.
  • Dennet, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and Meanings of Life. New York: Simon Schuster.
  • Detlef, L. (1999). Turning Points in the Conception of Mathematics, Bernhard Riemann 1826-1866. Boston: Birkhauser.
  • Elgin, M. (2003). Biology and A Priori Laws. Philosophy of Science, 70 (5), 1380-1389.
  • Elgin, M., Sober, E. (2017). Popper’s Shifting Appraisal of Evolutionary Theory. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 7: 1, 31-55.
  • Ferreiros, J. (2007). Labyrinth of Thought: a History of Set Theory and Its Role in Modern Mathematics. Basel, Switzerland; Boston: Birkhauser.
  • French, S. How to Avoid Desk Rejection. (Erişim Tarihi: 22.08.2020) Erişim Adresi: http://www.thebsps.org/auxhyp/deskrejectionfrench/
  • Giere, R.N. (1973). History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24 (3), 282–297.
  • Giere, R.N. (1999). Science Without Laws. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge University Press.
  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hawking, S. W., Mlodinov, L. (2010). The Grand Design. Bantam.
  • Howard, Don A. and Giovanelli, Marco (2019) "Einstein’s Philosophy of Science", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2019 Edition (Edward N. Zalta, Ed.), (Erişim Tarihi: 28.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/einstein-philscience/
  • Howard, D. (1984). Realism and Conventionalism in Einstein’s Philosophy of Science: The Einstein-Schlick Correspondence. Philosophia Naturalis 21, 618–629.
  • Howard, D. (1993). Was Einstein Really a Realist? Perspectives on Science: Historical, Philosophical, Social 1, 204–251.
  • Howard, D. (1994a). Einstein, Kant, and the Origins of Logical Empiricism. Language, Logic, and the Structure of Scientific Theories (Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Konstanz, 21–24 May 1991), Wesley Salmon and Gereon Wolters (Eds.) içinde (ss. 45–105). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press; Konstanz: Universitätsverlag.
  • Irzık, G. (2008, 24 Nisan). Felsefeci Gözüyle Bilimsel Devrim. Türkiye Bilimler Akademisi Toplantıları, Ankara.
  • Kitcher, P. (1998). A Plea for Science Studies. Noretta Koertge (Edt.) A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths About Science içinde (ss. 32-56). New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Knapton,S. (2018). Albert Einstein’s Theory of Relativity was inspired by Scottish philosopher. The Telegraph. (Erişim Tarihi: 28.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://www.telegraph.co.uk/science/2019/02/19/albert-einsteins-theory-relativity-inspired-scottish-philosopher/
  • Kuhn, T.S. (1980). The Halt and the Blind: Philosophy and History of Science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 31 (2), 181–192.
  • Lakatos, I. (1970). History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 91–136.
  • Laplanea, L., Mantovanic, P., Adolph, R., Chang, H., Mantovani, A., McFall-Ngai M., Rovellii C., Sober, E., Pradeu, T. (2019). Why Science Needs Philosophy. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116 (10), 3948-3952.
  • Laudan, L. (1990). The History of Science and the Philosophy of Science. (R. C. Olby, G. N. Cantor, J. R. R. Christie, M. J. S. Hodge, Eds.), Companion to the History of Modern Science içinde (ss. 47–59). Routledge.
  • Lewontin, R. C. (1995, 2 Kasım). Genes and Sexuality: An Exchange. The New York Review of Books. (Erişim Tarihi: 29.06.2020) Erişim adresi: https://www.nybooks.com/articles/1995/11/02/genes-and-sexuality-an-exchange/
  • Lynch, M. (1993). Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodology and Social Studies of Science. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mäki, U. (2011). Models and the Locus of Their Truth. Synthese, 180 (1), 47-63.
  • Markosian, Ned (2016) "Time", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition), (Edward N. Zalta, Ed.), (Erişim Tarihi: 25.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/time/
  • Mitchell, S. (1997). Pragmatic Laws. Philosophy of Science 64, 468-479.
  • Mitchell, S. (2000). Dimensions of Scientific Law. Philosophy of Science 67, 242-265.
  • Munafo, M.R. & Smith, G. D. (2018). Repeating experiments is not Enough. Nature, Vol. 553, 399-401.
  • Munafo, M.R., Smith, G. D. (2018). Philosophy of science isn't pointless chin-stroking – it makes us better scientists. The Guardian (Erişim Tarihi: 26.06.2020) Erişim adresi: https://www.theguardian.com/science/blog/2018/feb/01/philosophy-of-science-isnt-pointless-chin-stroking-it-makes-us-better-scientists
  • Musgrave, Alan; Pigden, Charles (2016) "Imre Lakatos", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), (Edward N. Zalta, Ed.), (Erişim Tarihi: 25.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/lakatos/
  • Norton, J. D. (2010). How Hume and Mach Helped Einstein to Find Special Relativity. Discourse on a New Method. Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science, Mary Domski et al. (Eds.) içinde (ss. 359‒387). Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.
  • Odenbaugh, J. (2005). Idealized, Inaccurate But Successful: A Pragmatic Approach to Evaluating Models in Ecology. Biology and Philosophy, 20 (2-3), 231-255.
  • Papineau, D. (2017). Is philosophy simply harder than science? (Erişim Tarihi: 24.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/public/philosophy-simply-harder-science/
  • Papineau, D. (2019). Felsefe Temel Olarak Bilimden Daha mı Zordur? (M.E. Ateş, Çev.) Yeni-e, Sayı 30.
  • Pickering, A. (Ed.). (1992). Science as Practice and Culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Putnam, H. (1967). Time and Physical Geometry. The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 64, No. 8, 240-247.
  • Raerinne, J. (2018). Abstraction in Ecology: Reductionism and Holism as Complementary Heuristics. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8, 395-416.
  • Reiss, J. (2013). Philosophy of Economics: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge.
  • Richards, R.J. (1992). Arguments in a Sartorial Mode, or the Asymmetries of History and Philosophy of Science. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 482–489.
  • Rohwer, Y., and Rice, C. (2013). Hypothetical Pattern Idealization and Explanatory Models. Philosophy of Science, 80, 334-355.
  • Rouse, J. (2002). How Scientifc Practices Matter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Rovelli, C. (2018). Physics Needs Philosophy / Philosophy Needs Physics. Scientific American, (Erişim Tarihi: 24.06.2020) Erişim Adresi: https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/physics-needs-philosophy-philosophy-needs-physics/
  • Russell, B. (1956). An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. New York: Dover Publications.
  • Santana, C. (2019). Waiting for Antropocene. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Volume 70, Sayı 4, 1073-1096.
  • Schatzki, T. R., Knorr-Cetina, K., & Von Savigny, E. (Eds.). (2001). The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory. London: Routledge.
  • Scholz, E. (1982). Herbart's influence on Bernhard Riemann. Historia Mathematica (9), 413-440.
  • Scott, C. D. (2012). The Death of Philosophy: A Response to Stephen Hawking. South African Journal of Philosophy, 31: 2, 384-404.
  • Shahvisi, A. (2016). Tainted: How Philosophy of Science Can Expose Bad Science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 30: 2, 193-196.
  • Slavov, M. (2016). Empiricism and Relationism Intertwined: Hume and Einstein's Special Theory of Relativity. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 31 (2), 247-263.
  • Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago, London: The University of Chicago Press.
  • Sober, E. (1997). Two Outbreaks of Lawness in Recent Philosophy of Biology. Philosophy of Science 64 (4), 458-467.
  • Soler, L. & Zwart, S. & Lynch, M. & Israel-Jost, V. (2014). Science After the Practice Turn in the Philosophy, History, and Social Studies of Science içinde (ss. 1-43). New York and London: Routledge.
  • Spencer, B. (2012). Sanity and Solitude: Cogent Ramblings of a Lone Aesthetic. UK: AuthorHouse.
  • Stern, D. (2003). The Practical Turn. The Blackwell Guidebook to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Stephen Turner and Paul Roth (Eds.) içinde (ss. 185-206). Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Torretti, R. (1978). Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincare. Dordrecht: Reidel: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
  • Turner, S. (1994). The Social Theory of Practices: Tradition, Tacit Knowledge and Presuppositions. Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • Van Fraassen, B.C. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Waters, C. K. (2014). Shifting Attention from Theory to Practice in Philosophy of Biology. M.C. Galavotti, D. Dieks, W.J. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, T. Uebel, and M. Weber (Eds.) New Directions in the Philosophy of Science içinde (ss. 121-139). Berlin: Springer International Publishing.
  • Waters, C. K. (2019). An Epistemology of Scientific Practice. Philosophy of Science, 86, 585–611.
  • Woodward, J. (2000). Explanation and Invariance in the Special Sciences. British Journal British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 197-254.
  • Woodward, J. (2001). Law and Explanation in Biology: Invariance is the Kind of Stability That Matters. Philosophy of Science, 68, 1-20.
  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Woody, A.I., (2014). Chemistry’s Periodic Law: Rethinking Representation and Explanation After the Turn to Practice. Science After the Practice Turn in the Philosophy, History, and Social Studies of Science içinde (ss. 123-150). New York and London: Routledge.